Jump directly to the Content
Jump directly to the content
Article

by David W. Gill


Toxic Maxims

Misleading advice about business ethics from America's leadership expert.

John C. Maxwell has built a large and apparently influential movement around his messages on leadership. His book The 21 Irrefutable Laws of Leadership was a bestseller, and his book jackets proclaim him "America's expert on leadership," adding that he speaks "in person" to more than 250,000 people each year. Precisely because he commands such an audience, Maxwell's latest little book, There's No Such Thing as "Business" Ethics, cannot simply be ignored as a harmless, lightweight compendium of folksy counsel, anecdotes, and lists (lots of lists). Woven through the book are two major points that must be challenged.

First, Maxwell boldly insists that there is no such thing as business ethics. What he means is that there is no such thing as a separate realm of ethics for business. Our values and ethics at home must be the same as at the club, in politics, in church, and in business. But Maxwell does not limit himself to the noncontroversial admonition that our core values and principles should be consistent throughout all areas of our life; he goes on to rule out any specialized focus on business ethics and to mischaracterize business ethics as an enterprise inherently bent on justifying behavior we would not tolerate in our personal lives. Not so.

Second, Maxwell insists that there is one and only one principle of sound ethics: do unto others what you would want them to do unto you. Some version of this principle, he points out, is fundamental to most of the world's religions. But rather than limiting himself to a brief reflection on what the Golden Rule can contribute to our ethics, he declares illegitimate and unnecessary all moral guidance beyond the Golden Rule.

Contra Maxwell, "business ethics" can be defined as "serious ethical reflection on matters of right and wrong, good and bad, in the business context." This definition requires no contradiction between personal ethics and business ethics. On the contrary, such a contradiction has always received its strongest support from those who say that "'business ethics' is an oxymoron" or "business operates like a game with its own unique rules" or "the market is an amoral, impersonal entity governed by an invisible hand, not by people's personal moral values." Business ethicists are usually people who work hard to bring serious moral reflection into our work, our commerce, our business organizations, and our economic life. Criticizing that effort, as Maxwell has done, is exactly the wrong thing to do in the age of Enron.

Maxwell defines an "ethical dilemma" as "an undesirable or unpleasant choice relating to a moral principle or practice"—a choice between "the easy thing or the right thing" Again, a very naÏve and misleading position to take. Most ethical dilemmas are such not because of "easy versus right" but because of the difficulty of figuring out the right thing to do. Should we lay off these loyal workers, getting close to retirement, and move their jobs offshore in order to increase profits, and possibly lower costs to customers? Should we share our research on this pharmaceutical project with our competitors to advance the pace of discovering a cure for this disease? Such dilemmas are constituted by serious conflicts of values and by complex circumstances requiring careful, focused attention and analysis, not a simplistic dismissal.

One thing a good course in business ethics could do for Maxwell is teach him the differences between such things as corporate culture, organizational structure and policy, personal character, and decision-making. He writes about the importance of character, for example, but offers no real insight into just what character is, how it is formed, or how it relates to decision-making, community, or diversity. Nor does Maxwell show any awareness of how structures and policies are laden with values and why, thus, it is critical not just to call for more ethical individuals but for procedural and organizational reforms.

There is an astonishing naÏvetÉ in Maxwell's discussions of both business and ethics. The following ("always/never") overstatement is typical: "One of our problems is that ethics is never a business issue or a social issue or a political issue. It is always a personal issue." And here is an example—just one of many—of his reductionism ("only"): "There are really only two important points when it comes to ethics. The first is a standard to follow. The second is the will to follow it." Only these two points are important in ethics? Uh, what about the challenge of interpreting and applying the standard in this or that circumstance or context?

Maxwell's second message is that "there's only one rule for making decisions"—the Golden Rule. Now there is no doubt about the broad applicability and general helpfulness of the Golden Rule. Maxwell has some occasionally helpful comments about how this rule might be deployed, though he is far from precise in defining, explaining, or applying it. It is not so simple or self-evident as he wishes.

On the surface at least, the Golden Rule says to "do unto others what you would have others do to you." Question: What should I do? Answer: Whatever I would want done to me. It is a self-referential process. Would I want to be treated fairly? Yes. Therefore I should treat others fairly. But it is not quite so simple all the time. Personally, I like people to confront me with their brutal, unvarnished opinions, no holds barred. Should I then speak equally brutally and frankly to all others? Not necessarily. It is not always enough simply to generalize based on my personal preferences and impute them to others. It is one good test question, but not sufficient by itself. The Golden Rule can be corrupted into a self-centered imperialism. Isn't it important also to make a place for "Do unto others as they want you to do to them"?

One irony of Maxwell's argument is that he attacks Joseph Fletcher's famous "situation ethics" as a source of today's moral relativism. He characterizes Fletcher's position as "If it's good for me, then it's good." And yet, like Maxwell, Fletcher reduces ethics to the application of a single rule—in Fletcher's case, "love your neighbor." Yes, this can be relativistic and situational, but note that at least it is focused not on "what I would want" (Golden Rule) but on "what would be loving for my neighbor?" Taken by itself, Maxwell's one rule is actually more egoistic than Fletcher's one rule (and equally situational and relativistic).

Both attempts to propose one single, stand-alone rule of ethics are simplistic and fundamentally wrong. As a pastor for many years, Maxwell ought to remember that there are at least two important qualifications to the Golden Rule provided by Jesus in the Sermon on the Mount. First, the Golden Rule is given to a band of disciples, not to a Lone Ranger decision-maker. Character formation and ethical decision-making are a "team sport," a community enterprise, not a matter entrusted to American-style "rugged individualists." The safeguards lie in discussing "what would we want done to us" rather than "what would I want done to me." The Golden Rule is not being taught accurately and faithfully if it is submitted to the runaway individualism and narcissism of our era.

Although he makes a brief and undeveloped pitch for "accountability," Maxwell dismisses the general, positive potential of community and teamwork in ethics: "The more people involved, the greater the pressure for conformity." If Maxwell had explored the potential uses of the Golden Rule by business teams in today's environment (electronically connected, culturally diverse, globally extended, blistering pace, rapid employee turnover), he might have made a valuable contribution, faithful to the sources as well as practical and relevant in its interpretation and application. Instead he reads it through the tired lenses of modernity and American individualism.

Second, the Golden Rule is not the only rule for making decisions—not in business ethics, and not in Christian ethics. It is a great summary rule, but it is not the only one. Jesus also taught the Love Commandments (Love God, Love your neighbor as yourself) and a whole lot more. Jesus taught the generality of the Golden Rule; he did not teach the exclusivity of the Golden Rule.

Furthermore, Jesus didn't just teach principles and rules of decision-making—he taught people about the traits of good, healthy character and community, and he taught people to reflect on the larger life purposes which alone can motivate and leverage behavioral change. What Jesus taught was a richly textured approach to the moral life. Jesus had more to say, by the way, about money, property, and wealth (business ethics!) than about heaven and hell or lots of other religious topics. Jesus and Christian ethics should not be blamed for the misrepresentations of Maxwell's book.

John Maxwell could be thought of as providing a sort of Headline News Network or USA Today level of teaching, especially in this ethics book: brief bits and pieces in simple language, seeking to capture a momentary glance in our frantic, distracted age. No big concern for depth or continuity. Ken Blanchard and Michael O'Conner's little book Managing by Values (Berrett-Koehler, 1997) and Max DePree's Leadership Is an Art (Doubleday, 1989) are two examples of how to do this well. I am certainly not interested in defending the boring, irrelevant mountains of words written by many of us in business ethics. My objection to Maxwell's book is not to its genre or to his basic project.

The problem is twofold. First, the "HNN" version ought to be true as far as it goes. It may be short and simplified, but it ought to be right. Maxwell's book offers some advice here and there that may be helpful to some readers but its overall thesis, its definitions, its representations of business ethics and of the Golden Rule are badly flawed if not flat-out wrong much of the time.

Second, the HNN approach may have a legitimate place in the sun, but its devotees must not say that that place is the only legitimate one. The HNN producers and consumers must not say that there is no place for the deeper approaches provided by NPR, Frontline, Bill Moyers, the Jim Lehrer Newshour, Ted Koppel's Nightline, and 60 Minutes. In effect this is what Maxwell is saying: there is no such thing as business ethics— there is just his little set of inadequate slogans and platitudes about the Golden Rule.

Over my morning coffee on the day I drafted this review, I read that Tyco crooks Dennis Kozlowski and Mark Swartz were finally being taken to court, that Pipevine was now exposed as owing more than $18 million to charities it defrauded while collecting donations, that Franklin Resources will now be investigated for possible illegal trading practices, and that Frank Quattrone was making excuses in court. And that was just page one in the business section.

These are not isolated incidents. They are part of an epidemic of unethical business leadership. This is no time to undercut efforts to focus attention on business ethics. I am sure that John Maxwell means well, and he must know a lot about leadership. But There's No Such Thing as "Business" Ethics is a misleading book that he should never have written. We do not need "no business ethics"—we need much more and much better business ethics.

David W. Gill is a business ethics writer, consultant, and educator based in the San Francisco Bay Area (www.ethixbiz.com). He is the author or editor of six books, including Doing Right: Practicing Ethical Principles, forthcoming from InterVarsity this summer.


Most ReadMost Shared